哥德爾可構(gòu)造宇宙

Ordinals: the transfinite numbers
I ? is the smallest ordinal: this is 0.
I {?} is the next ordinal: this is 1.
I {?, {?}} is next ordinal: this is 2.
If α is an ordinal then
I α is just the set of all ordinals β such that β is smaller than α,
I α + 1 = α ∪ {α} is the next largest ordinal.
ω denotes the least infinite ordinal, it is the set of all finite ordinals.
V: The Universe of Sets
The power set
Suppose X is a set. The powerset of X is the set
P(X) = {Y Y is a subset of X}.
Cumulative Hierarchy of Sets
The universe V of sets is generated by defining Vα by induction on
the ordinal α:
1. V0 = ?,
2. Vα+1 = P(Vα),
3. if α is a limit ordinal then Vα =
S
β<α Vβ.
I If X is a set then X ∈ Vα for some ordinal α.
I V0 = ?, V1 = {?}, V2 = {?, {?}}.
I These are just the ordinals: 0, 1, and 2.
I V3 has 4 elements (and is clearly not an ordinal).
I V4 has 16 elements.
I V5 has 65, 536 elements.
I V1000 has a lot of elements.
Vω is infinite, it is the set of all (hereditarily) finite sets.
The conception of Vω is mathematically identical to the
conception of the structure (N, +, ·):
I Each structure can be interpreted in the other structure.
Beyond the basic axioms: large cardinal axioms
Shaping the conception of V
I The ZFC axioms of Set Theory formally specify the founding
principles for the conception of V.
I The ZFC axioms are naturally augmented by additional
axioms which assert the existence of “very large” infinite sets.
I Such axioms assert the existence of large cardinals.
These large cardinals include:
I Measurable cardinals
I Strong cardinals
I Woodin cardinals
I Superstrong cardinals
I Supercompact cardinals
I Extendible cardinals
I Huge cardinals
I ω-huge cardinals
Cardinality: measuring the size of sets
Definition: when two sets have the same size
Two sets, X and Y , have the same cardinality if there is a
matching of the elements of X with the elements of Y .
Formally: |X| = |Y | if there is a bijection
f : X → Y
Assuming the Axiom of Choice which is one of the ZFC axioms:
Theorem (Cantor)
For every set X there is an ordinal α such that |X| = |α|.
The Continuum Hypothesis: CH
Theorem (Cantor)
The set N of all natural numbers and the set R of all real numbers
do not have the same cardinality.
I There really are different “sizes” of infinity!
The Continuum Hypothesis
Suppose A ? R is infinite. Then either:
1. A and N have the same cardinality, or
2. A and R have the same cardinality.
I This is Cantor’s Continuum Hypothesis.
Many tried to solve the problem of the Continuum
Hypothesis and failed.
The problem of the Continuum Hypothesis quickly came to be
widely regarded as one of the most important problems in all of
modern Mathematics.
In 1940, G¨odel showed that it is consistent with the axioms of Set
Theory that the Continuum Hypothesis be true.
I One cannot refute the Continuum Hypothesis.
In 1963, on July 4th, Cohen announced in a lecture at Berkeley
that it is consistent with the axioms of Set Theory that the
Continuum Hypothesis be false.
I One cannot prove the Continuum Hypothesis.
Cohen’s method
If M is a model of ZFC then M contains “blueprints” for virtual
models N of ZFC, which enlarge M. These blueprints can be
constructed and analyzed from within M.
I If M is countable then every blueprint constructed within M
can be realized as genuine enlargement of M.
I Cohen proved that every model of ZFC contains a blueprint
for an enlargement in which the Continuum Hypothesis is
false.
I Cohen’s method also shows that every model of ZFC
contains a blueprint for an enlargement in which the
Continuum Hypothesis is true.
I (Levy-Solovay) These enlargements preserve large cardinal
axioms:
I So if large cardinal axioms can help
I it can only be in some unexpected way.
The extent of Cohen’s method: It is not just about CH
A challenging time for the conception of V
I Cohen’s method has been vastly developed in the 5 decades
since Cohen’s original work.
I Many problems have been showed to be unsolvable including
problems outside Set Theory:
I (Group Theory) Whitehead Problem (Shelah)
I (Analysis) Kaplansky’s Conjecture (Solovay)
I (Combinatorics of the real line) Suslin’s Problem
(Solovay-Tennenbaum, Jensen, Jech)
I (Measure Theory) Borel Conjecture (Laver)
I (Operator Algebras) Brown-Douglas-Filmore Automorphism
Problem (Phillips-Weaver, Farah)
I This is a serious challenge to the very conception of
Mathematical Infinity.
I These examples, including the Continuum Hypothesis, are all
statements about just Vω+2.
Ok, maybe it is just time to give up
Claim
I Large cardinal axioms are not provable;
I by G¨odel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem.
I But, large cardinal axioms are falsifiable.
Prediction
No contradiction from the existence of infinitely many Woodin
cardinals will be discovered within the next 1000 years.
I Not by any means whatsoever.
Truth beyond our formal reach
The real claim of course is:
I There is no contradiction from the existence of infinitely
many Woodin cardinals.
Claim
I Such statements cannot be formally proved.
I This suggests there is a component in the evolution of
our understanding of Mathematics which is not formal.
I There is mathematical knowledge which is not
entirely based in proofs.
Claim
The skeptical assessment that the conception of the universe
of sets is incoherent, must be wrong.
I How else can these truths and ensuing predictions be
explained?
I But then either CH must be true or CH must be false.
OK, back to the problem of the Continuum Hypothesis
The skeptic’s challenge
Resolve the problem of CH.
I Perhaps one should begin by trying to more deeply understand
CH.
A natural conjecture
One can more deeply understand CH by looking at special cases.
I But which special cases?
I Does this even make sense?
The simplest uncountable sets
Definition
A set A ? Vω+1 is a projective set if:
I A can be logically defined in the structure
(Vω+1, ∈)
from parameters.
We can easily extend the definition to relations on Vω+1:
Definition
A set A ? Vω+1 × Vω+1 is a projective set if:
I A can be logically defined as a binary relation in the structure
(Vω+1, ∈)
from parameters.
I The countable subsets of Vω+1 and Vω+1 × Vω+1 are
projective sets but so are Vω+1 and Vω+1 × Vω+1 themselves,
and these sets are not countable.
The Continuum Hypothesis and the Projective Sets
The Continuum Hypothesis
Suppose A ? Vω+1 is infinite. Then either:
1. A and Vω have the same cardinality, or
2. A and Vω+1 have the same cardinality.
I This is a statement about all subsets of Vω+1.
The projective Continuum Hypothesis
Suppose A ? Vω+1 is an infinite projective set. Then either:
1. A and Vω have the same cardinality, or
2. There is a bijection
F : Vω+1 → A
such that F is a projective set.
I This is a statement about just the “simple” subsets of Vω+1.
The Axiom of Choice
Definition
Suppose that
A ? X × Y
A function
F : X → Y
is a choice function for A if for all a ∈ X:
I If there exists b ∈ Y such that (a, b) ∈ A then (a, F(a)) ∈ A.
The Axiom of Choice
For every set
A ? X × Y
there exists a choice function for A.
The Axiom of Choice and the Projective Sets
The projective Axiom of Choice
Suppose A ? Vω+1 × Vω+1 is a projective set. Then there is a
function
F : Vω+1 → Vω+1
such that:
I F is a choice function for A.
I F is a projective set.
I There were many attempts in the early 1900s to solve both
the problem of projective Continuum Hypothesis and the
problem of the projective Axiom of Choice:
I Achieving success for the simplest instances.
I However, by 1925 these problems both looked hopeless.
These were both hopeless problems
The actual constructions of G¨odel and Cohen show that both
problems are formally unsolvable.
I In G¨odel’s universe L:
I The projective Axiom of Choice holds.
I The projective Continuum Hypothesis holds.
I In the Cohen enlargement of L (as given by the actual
blueprint which Cohen defined for the failure of CH):
I The projective Axiom of Choice is false.
I The projective Continuum Hypothesis is false.
I This explains why these problems were so difficult.
I But the intuition that these problems are solvable was
correct.
An unexpected entanglement
Theorem (1984)
Suppose there are infinitely many Woodin cardinals. Then:
I The projective Continuum Hypothesis holds.
Theorem (1985: Martin-Steel)
Suppose there are infinitely many Woodin cardinals. Then:
I The projective Axiom of Choice holds.
We now have the correct conception of Vω+1 and the projective
sets.
I This conception yields axioms for the projective sets.
I These (determinacy) axioms in turn are closely related to
(and follow from) large cardinal axioms.
But what about Vω+2? Or even V itself?
Logical definability
The definable power set
For each set X, PDef(X) denotes the set of all Y ? X such that Y
is logically definable in the structure (X, ∈) from parameters in X.
I PDef(X) is the collection of just those subsets of X which are
intrinsic to X itself,
I versus P(X) which is the collection of all subsets of X.
The collection of all the projective subsets of Vω+1 is exactly
given by:
PDef(Vω+1)
The effective cumulative hierarchy: L
Cumulative Hierarchy of Sets
The cumulative hierarchy is defined by induction on α as follows.
1. V0 = ?.
2. Vα+1 = P(Vα).
3. if α is a limit ordinal then Vα =
S
β<α Vβ.
I V is the class of all sets X such that X ∈ Vα for some α.
G¨odel’s constructible universe, L
Define Lα by induction on α as follows.
1. L0 = ?.
2. Lα+1 = PDef(Lα).
3. if α is a limit ordinal then Lα = ∪{Lβ β < α}.
I L is the class of all sets X such that X ∈ Lα for some α.
The missing axiom for V?
The axiom: V = L
Suppose X is a set. Then X ∈ L.
Theorem (G¨odel:1940)
Assume V = L. Then the Continuum Hypothesis holds.
I Suppose there is a Cohen-blueprint for V = L. Then:
I the axiom V = L must hold and the blueprint is trivial.
Claim
Adopting the axiom V = L completely negates the ramifications of
Cohen’s method.
I Could this be the resolution?
I No, there is a serious problem.
The axiom V = L and large cardinals
Theorem (Scott:1961)
Assume V = L. Then there are no measurable cardinals.
I In fact there are no ( genuine ) large cardinals.
I Assume V = L. Then there are no Woodin cardinals.
Clearly:
The axiom V = L is false.
A natural conjecture
Perhaps the key is to generalize the construction of L by using the
large cardinals to expand the definable powerset operation.
I But there is an alternative approach which is based on simply
using the large cardinals to directly generalize the projective
sets.
Another way to define the projective sets
Observation
Vω+1 is homeomorphic to the Cantor set, with the topology on
Vω+1 given by the sets
On,a = {X ? Vω X ∩ Vn = a}
as basic open sets where n < ω and a ∈ Vn+1.
I The projective subsets of Vω+1 are exactly the sets generated
from the open sets and closing under the operations:
I Taking images by continuous functions
F : Vω+1 → Vω+1.
I Taking complements.
I This definition generalizes to any topological space.
I In particular, this extends the notion of the projective sets to
the Euclidean spaces R
n
.
Universally Baire sets
Definition (Feng-Magidor-Woodin)
A set A ? R
n
is universally Baire if:
I For all topological spaces ?
I For all continuous functions π : ? → R
n
;
the preimage of A by π has the property of Baire in the space ?.
I Universally Baire sets have the property of Baire
I Simply take ? = R
n
and π to be the identity.
I Universally Baire sets are Lebesgue measurable.
Theorem
Assume V = L. Then every set A ? R is the image of a universally
Baire set by a continuous function
F : R → R.
L(A, R) where A ? R
Relativizing L to A ? R
Suppose A ? R. Define Lα(A, R) by induction on α by:
1. L0(A, R) = Vω+1 ∪ {A},
2. (Successor case) Lα+1(A, R) = PDef(Lα(A, R)),
3. (Limit case) Lα(A, R) = ∪{Lβ(A, R) β < α}.
I L(A, R) is the class of all sets X such that X ∈ Lα(A, R) for
some ordinal α.
I P(R) ∩ Lω1
(A, R) is the smallest σ-algebra containing A and
closed under images by continuous functions f : R → R.
I If B ? R and B ∈ L(A, R) then L(B, R) ? L(A, R). So:
I P(R) ∩ L(A, R) is closed under images by continuous functions
F : R → R.
The universally Baire sets are the ultimate generalization
of the projective sets
Theorem
Suppose that there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and
suppose A ? R is universally Baire.
I Then every set B ∈ L(A, R) ∩ P(R) is universally Baire.
I Thus every projective set is universally Baire.
I Since clearly there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals.
Theorem
Suppose that there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals.
(1) (Martin-Steel) Suppose A ? R is universally Baire.
I Then A is determined.
(2) (Steel) Suppose A ? R × R is universally Baire.
I Then A has a choice function which is universally Baire.
I Thus L(A, R) |= AD, where AD is the Axiom of Determinacy.
Measuring the complexity of universally Baire sets
Definition
Suppose A and B are subsets of R.
1. A is weakly Wadge reducible to B, A ≤Wadge B, if there is
a function π : R → R such that:
I π is continuous on R\Q.
I Either A = π
?1
[B] or A = R\π
?1
[B].
2. A and B are weakly Wadge bi-reducible if
I A ≤Wadge B and B ≤Wadge A.
3. The weak Wadge degree of A is the equivalence class of all
sets which are weakly Wadge bi-reducible with A.
I If A is weakly Wadge reducible to B and B is universally Baire
then A is universally Baire.
An indication of deep structure
Theorem (Martin-Steel, Martin, Wadge)
Assume there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals.
Then the weak Wadge degrees of the universally Baire sets are
linearly ordered by weak Wadge reducibility and moreover this is a
wellorder.
Speculation
Perhaps this ultimate generalization of the projective sets can lead
us to the ultimate generalization of the axiom V = L.
I But how?
Defining the axiom V = L without defining L
A sentence ? is a Σ2-sentence if it is of the form:
I There exists an ordinal α such that Vα |= ψ;
for some sentence ψ.
For each ordinal α, let
Nα = ∩{M M is transitive, M |= ZFC\Powerset, and OrdM = α}.
where:
I A set M is transitive if a ? M for each a ∈ M.
Lemma
The following are equivalent.
(1) V = L.
(2) For each Σ2-sentence ?, if V |= ? then there exists a
countable ordinal α such that Nα |= ?.
I We need to somehow use the universally Baire sets in a
reformulation of (2).
G¨odel’s transitive class HOD
Definition
HOD is the class of all sets X such that there exist α ∈ Ord and
M ∈ Vα such that
1. X ∈ M and M is transitive.
2. Every element of M is definable in Vα from ordinal
parameters.
I For every set b there is a minimum transitive set TC(b) which
contains b as an element.
Why HOD?
Suppose N is a model of ZF. Let HODN ? N be HOD as defined
within N. Then for each b ∈ N, the following are equivalent:
1. b ∈ HODN.
2. Every element of (TC(b))N
is definable in N with parameters
from the ordinals of N.
HODL(A,R)
and measurable cardinals
Definition
Suppose that A ? R. Then HODL(A,R)
is the class HOD as
defined within L(A, R).
I The Axiom of Choice must hold in HODL(A,R)
I even if L(A, R) |= AD.
Theorem (Solovay:1967)
Suppose that A ? R and L(A, R) |= AD.
I Then ω
V
1
is a measurable cardinal in HODL(A,R)
.
I Solovay’s theorem gave the first connection between the
Axiom of Determinacy (AD) and large cardinal axioms.
HODL(A,R)
and Woodin cardinals
Theorem
Suppose that there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that
A is universally Baire.
I Then ω
V
1
is the least measurable cardinal in HODL(A,R)
.
Definition
Suppose that A ? R is universally Baire.
Then ΘL(A,R)
is the supremum of the ordinals α such that there is
a surjection, π : R → α, such that π ∈ L(A, R).
I ΘL(A,R)
is another measure of the complexity of A.
Theorem
Suppose that there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and that
A is universally Baire.
I Then ΘL(A,R)
is a Woodin cardinal in HODL(A,R)
.
The axiom V = Ultimate-L
I The existence of a Woodin cardinal is expressible by a
Σ2-sentence.
I Woodin cardinals clearly exist in V;
I If A ? R is universally Baire and there is a proper class of
Woodin cardinals then
HODL(A,R)
|= “There is a Woodin cardinal”.
The axiom for V = Ultimate-L
I There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals.
I For each Σ2-sentence ?, if ? holds in V then there is a
universally Baire set A ? R such that
HODL(A,R)
|= ?.
This is just rank resemblance
Assume there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals. Then the
following are equivalent:
I V = Ultimate-L.
I Suppose ψ is a sentence and there exists an ordinal α such
that
Vα |= ψ.
I Then there exists a universally Baire set A ? R such that
HODL(A,R)
|= “There exists α such that Vα |= ψ”
Some consequences of V = Ultimate-L
Theorem (V = Ultimate-L)
The Continuum Hypothesis holds.
Theorem (V = Ultimate-L)
V = HOD.
Theorem (V = Ultimate-L)
Let ?!?be the set of all universally Baire sets A ? R. Then
Γ
∞ 6= P(R) ∩ L(Γ∞, R)
If V = Ultimate-L then:
I The Axiom of Choice holds in L(?!? R).
I This is the generalization to V = Ultimate-L of the fact that
if V = L then there is a projective wellordering of the reals.
The axiom V = Ultimate-L and Cohen’s method
I Suppose there is a Cohen-blueprint for V = Ultimate-L.
Then:
I The axiom V = Ultimate-L must hold and the blueprint is
trivial.
I The axiom V = Ultimate-L settles (modulo axioms of
infinity) all sentences about “small” sets (like Vω+2) which
have been shown to be independent by Cohen’s method.
Claim
Adopting the axiom V = Ultimate-L completely negates the
ramifications of Cohen’s method.
I But, is the axiom V = Ultimate-L compatible with all large
cardinal axioms?
I Is there a Scott Theorem for V = Ultimate-L?
The language of large cardinals: elementary embeddings
Definition
Suppose X and Y are transitive sets. A function j : X → Y is an
elementary embedding if for all logical formulas ?[x0, . . . , xn]
and all a0, . . . , an ∈ X,
(X, ∈) |= ?[a0, . . . , an] if and only if (Y , ∈) |= ?[j(a0), . . . , j(an)]
I Isomorphisms are elementary embeddings but the only
isomorphisms of (X, ∈) and (Y , ∈) are trivial.
Lemma
Suppose that j : Vα → Vβ is an elementary embedding. Then the
following are equivalent.
(1) j is not the identity.
(2) There is an ordinal η < α such that j(η) 6= η.
I CRT(j) denotes the least ordinal η such that j(η) 6= η.
Extendible cardinals and supercompact cardinals
Definition (Reinhardt:(1974))
Suppose that δ is a cardinal.
I Then δ is an extendible cardinal if for each λ > δ there
exists an elementary embedding
j : Vλ+1 → Vj(λ)+1
such that CRT(j) = δ and j(δ) > λ.
Definition (Solovay, Reinhardt: as reformulated by Magidor(1971))
Suppose that δ is a cardinal.
I Then δ is an supercompact cardinal if for each λ > δ there
exist δ <ˉ λ < δ ˉ and an elementary embedding
j : Vλˉ+1 → Vλ+1
such that CRT(j) = δˉ and j(δˉ) = δ.
Weak extender models
Definition
Suppose N is a transitive class, N contains the ordinals, and that
N is a model of ZFC.
I Then N is a weak extender model of δ is supercompact if
for every γ > δ there exist δ <ˉ λ < δ ˉ and an elementary
embedding
π : Vλˉ+1 → Vλ+1
such that CRT(π) = δ
ˉ, π(δ
ˉ) = δ, and such that
I π(N ∩ Vλˉ ) = N ∩ Vλ.
I π|(N ∩ Vλˉ ) ∈ N.
Suppose N is a weak extender model of δ is supercompact and
that α ≥ δ
+.
I N is uniquely specified by N ∩ Vα.
I N is Σ2-definable from N ∩ Vα.
I The theory of weak extender models is part of the theory of V.
Large cardinals above δ are downward absolute to weak
extender models of δ is supercompact
Theorem
Suppose that N is a weak extender model of δ is supercompact,
κ > δ, and that κ is an extendible cardinal.
I Then κ is an extendible cardinal in N.
Theorem
Suppose that N is a weak extender model of δ is supercompact,
κ > δ, and that κ is a supercompact cardinal.
I Then κ is a supercompact cardinal in N.
I There are generalizations of this for all large cardinal notions.
The Universality Theorem
Theorem (Universality Theorem)
Suppose that N is a weak extender model of δ is supercompact,
α > δ is a limit ordinal, and that
j : Vα+2 → Vj(α)+2
is an elementary embedding such that δ < CRT(j). Then:
I j(N ∩ Vα) = N ∩ Vj(α)
.
I j|(N ∩ Vα) ∈ N.
I Conclusion: There can be no generalization of Scott’s
Theorem to any axiom which holds in some weak extender
model of δ is supercompact, for any δ.
The Ultimate-L Conjecture
Ultimate-L Conjecture
(ZFC) Suppose that δ is an extendible cardinal. Then (provably)
there is a transitive class N such that:
1. N is a weak extender model of δ is supercompact.
2. N |= “V = Ultimate-L”.
I The Ultimate-L Conjecture implies there is no generalization
of Scott’s theorem to the axiom V = Ultimate-L.
I By the Universality Theorem.
I The Ultimate-L Conjecture is an existential number theoretic
statement.
I If it is undecidable then it must be false.
Claim
The Ultimate-L Conjecture must be either true or false
I it cannot be meaningless.
Set Theory faces one of two futures
I The Ultimate-L Conjecture reduces the entire post-Cohen
debate on Set Theoretic truth to a single question which
I must have an answer.
Future 1: The Ultimate-L Conjecture is true.
I Then the axiom V = Ultimate-L is very likely the key missing
axiom for V.
I There is no generalization of Scott’s Theorem for the axiom
V = Ultimate-L.
I All the questions which have been shown to be unsolvable by
Cohen’s method are resolved modulo large cardinal axioms.
Future 2: The Ultimate-L Conjecture is false.
I Then the program to understand V by generalizing the
success in understanding Vω+1 and the projective sets fails.
I Which is it?